Wednesday, April 30, 2014

Punch Magazine and the Golden Age. . . .

My father was born on Thursday,  March 24, three days short of Easter in 1932. I am only aware of the proximity of his birth to Easter Sunday because of a cartoon that appeared in Punch Magazine on that week. Here is the cartoon.
The cartoon is by Bernard Partridge, an artist who became the chief cartoonist at Punch Magazine around 1910 and continued to do cartoons, book illustrations, and some paintings till his death in 1945. The cartoon is meant to illustrate the irregularity of the timing of the Easter Holiday, and though it is not particularly amusing, it is a nice drawing and, entirely unbeknownst to Mr. Partridge, it informed me of a little piece of trivia about my father's birth. 

My dad loved Punch Magazine and left me a large collection of Punch books which are collections of cartoons and writings. Punch was one of the longest running magazines of England. Punch published from 1841 to 2002 and some great writers were involved in it pages including my very favourite writer E.V. Lucas.  One of the most interesting aspects of Punch is that, in a country so infected by class distinctions, it crossed over class fairly effectively. Punch was by no means a radical publication, but one of the very first editions of Punch contained Thomas Hood's great poetic indictment of English Capitalism "The Song of the Shirt" which was transformed into a popular song and was an integral piece of the cultural puzzle leading to labour reforms.* Punch seemed to appeal to people of all walks of life and in it offices were brought together working-class writers and artists as well as wealthy ones. My father was very working-class but he always enjoyed Punch not only as an artist but as someone who enjoyed good and amusing prose. 

Punch is probably more remembered for the artwork that appeared on its pages than for the great prose. One of Punch's greatest artists, Charles Keene, was a globally admired etcher and pen and ink artist who was so effective (so the legend goes) that he was a significant influence on great painters of the 19th century. Here is an example of Keene's work. 


But Charles Keene was of the 19th century in style and Bernard Partridge, though a good draughtsman, often produced rather stiff and overly heavy work. My father's personal favourite Punch cartoonist was unquestionably the great Phil May. Though May died in 1903, his style was revolutionary and he introduced a real 20th century style. May eschewed the traditional pen and ink approach and invented a simplified, fluid style that gives him a very important place in the history of cartooning and drawing in general. (I was lucky enough to inherit an original Phil May cartoon from my dad) Take a look at this drawing which is remarkably open and minimal for a 19th century work in pen and ink. 

My dad was particularly attracted to Phil May because he often portrayed working-class, cockneys on the streets of London in sympathetic, amusing ways. May's "Gutter-snipe" series is a genuine and important historical record of working-class culture. 

My favourite Punch cartoonist of the golden age is, without a doubt, Frank Reynolds. Reynolds was a remarkable draughtsman and could draw better than almost anyone I have ever seen. He was, for a number of years, the art editor of Punch as well as a prolific watercolour painter. Here is one of my favourite Reynolds cartoons from the pages of Punch. 

Punch is gone now. But more importantly, the era of drawing is largely gone. When I was in art college I was a drawing major and I spent years trying to continually improve my drawing skills. And even though my work doesn't generally involve complex, realistic drawings, I know that the skill helps me in every kind of artwork. But we live in a different era today and most artwork I see is woefully inadequate from a drawing point of view. It is unfortunate because I often see paintings, for example, in which the message is significantly let down by the artist's inability to draw effectively. This situation has gotten so dramatic that I believe that much of the time artists don't even know when their drawing skills are lacking. But we live in an age of short-hand, and the skills that were once considered "basic" for an artist are being replaced by more complex computer and digital skills. So it goes. 

But I have digressed. I read Punch collections regularly for the enjoyment of the drawings, the humour, and the excellent prose. But I also look at such books as a way of connecting me to the past. The pages of Punch connect me to my father (as the Bernard Partridge example so effectively illustrates) and to the writing, art, and culture of the past. 


*It should also be remembered that one of Punch's founding editors was Henry Mayhew who wrote one of the first effective sociological studies in English - London Labour and the London Poor. He was a man who knew first hand the terrible conditions in which many in England lived at that time. 

Tuesday, April 22, 2014

The Dilemma of Painting's Function. . . .

There are a seemingly countless number of motivations for producing and consuming art in the modern world. For some, art is a form of escape and pure entertainment. Others want art to challenge their world view and stir them from complacency. Art can be an act of personal therapy or a revolutionary effort. This variety in art's function and meaning led German philosopher Theodor Adorno to open his book of aesthetic theory with the observation that "today, it goes without saying that nothing about art goes without saying." However, for much of the history of the arts it could be argued that they have had a primary function that is generally instructive, at least in an abstract sense. Before the modern era much of that which we now call "art" (that is to say that which functioned beyond what we now refer to as craft) was religious or moralistic in nature. From renaissance painting to 19th century moralist novels, art has often served a fairly didactic role. Even Romantic poetry was often perceived to have an ethical function by many of its practitioners. Shelley was a master of cadence and lyrical verse, but he didn't write poetry for poetry's sake. Even the shorter poems among his masterpieces, such as the brilliant "Lines Written Among the Euganean Hills" is meant to teach its reader about life. Consider the opening lines -

Many a green isle needs must be
In the deep wide sea of misery -
Or the mariner, worn and wan,
Never thus could voyage on.

If we return to Ruskin, who I have been discussing recently, we can see that one of the reasons for his significant success is found, as George Landow has pointed out, in his ethical, sermonic style which appealed to his moralistic, Victorian readers. Even today, though a didactic concept of art is decidedly unfashionable, many people read novels in a rather instructive way. I obviously don't mean to imply that people are expecting their novels to teach them how to use a smart-phone or change a tire. But they do seem to expect their novels to be more than mere entertainment, and often look for stories to demonstrate how people navigate the complex moral dilemmas and social intricacies in their lives as though they are reading an abstract form of self-help book.

Within the field of visual art there is a long history of instructive material. From renaissance paintings that illustrate biblical stories to the instructions on how to construct Ikea furniture, there are many examples of visual art performing a specifically didactic function. This is a realm of art that was compellingly addressed by James Elkins in his 1999 book The Domain of Images. However, since the modern era, I think it is safe to say that, in terms of instructive power, the primary visual "high" art has been at something of a disadvantage compared to art forms such as, say, literature or theatre. Instead of embracing a directly didactic function, many people see visual art in terms of the ways in which it can raise the profundity of our thoughts and seize upon the sublimity of the natural world. Indeed, this is precisely what Ruskin imagined that the essential role of great art to be. (Obviously the more 'commercial' visual art forms are an entirely different story)

To return to where I began, I would say that these issues raise a dilemma that has faced art in general, but most specifically visual art, since the beginning of the modern age; the dilemma of function. When the specifically religious function of visual art began to disappear, visual art (specifically painting) became more or less the handmaiden of rich and powerful. In terms of its necessary social investment, painting is very expensive; it takes a long time to train a painter and most paintings are very labour intensive. This relative social expense made "fine" art the domain of only the few who could afford the investment. With the growth of the middle-class, the possible audience for 'fine' art expanded somewhat and many painters turned to decorative art (landscapes in particular) as a possible outlet for an artistic career.* But as Romantic ideology became ingrained in the culture of art, and art became more and more a question of personal expression, the function of painting became increasingly problematic. This dilemma is characterized by the fact that we have had generations of 'fine' artists who have overwhelmingly operated in isolation and anonymity. The reason for this dilemma goes back to the issue with which I began this discussion - didacticism. I think it is relatively straightforward for novels, films, theatre, or even video games to serve multiple functions. Such art forms can easily be personal expressions of their authors, entertainments, cultural documents, and morally instructive all at the same time. However, this multi-functional effort seems to be a much more difficult project for a painting. In other words, though visual art in the so-called commercial field is remarkably dynamic in its possible functions, an art form like painting is quite limited in scope compared to other art forms.

Now this a significantly truncated argument and one could write a large book fleshing out the issues raised here such as the relationship between the rise of Romanticism and capitalism, the so-called "free-market" and the emphasis on individual creativity, etc. But I think the core of the argument is fairly basic - an art form like painting, with its inherent narrative limits and its stress on the individual creative process has a difficult time thriving in a modern, technologically driven culture and market, particularly given the versatility of other art forms which can be at once didactic (or perhaps we should say 'informative'), technologically engaging, entertaining, seductively decorative, and simultaneously universal as well as personal.

I have my own, deeply personal, reasons for painting, and I don't kid myself that in an age of video games, block-buster movies, and e-readers, that painting could ever wield the kind of cultural currency that it once had. Of course, with the right recipe of luck and salesmanship, one could still earn a good living painting pictures. But like many time consuming crafts, painting is increasingly a marginalized activity. I suspect that in a world dominated by impersonal mass-production, some people will come to cherish the few things that can still have that human touch. But that will never really take art forms like painting out of the shadows of the global marketplace. As an advocate of the arts and crafts movement, I am certain that Ruskin would be horrified by the modern culture of mass-production. He wanted art to be not only a personal expression but an expression that lifted peoples lives and consciousness onto a higher plane, not only to demonstrate what we are but to demonstrate what we might become.

It is interesting that we spend thousands of dollars on objects in our lives (such as cars, computers, and cell phones) that are more or less disposable. And yet very few people go out and purchase art which is usually something that can last your own lifetime as well as the lifetimes of  many of your decedents. Similarly, it is amazing that people still routinely buy paperback books that are often destroyed after one reading while the internet now gives us access to countless high-quality, well bound, hard-cover books for very reasonable prices. I suspect that the reasons for this phenomenon is fairly straightforward; in a milieu of the speed and movement that comes with computer technology, we have begun to see the function of the arts as basically disposable like everything else. Films of remarkable quality come and go over a weekend. Books appear on our e-readers and then disappear. We are served a gluttonous diet of millions of visual images everyday that are like ghost in a digital dimension. When we have lost the aura that is associated with objects of art or craft, we have also largely lost our desires to preserve objects such as paintings and the lifetimes of pleasure that they can bring.


*It is interesting that one of the primary reactions to the functional dilemma of 'fine' art was the arts and crafts movements (led in large part by William Morris) which sought to deal with the declining importance of painting that came with capitalism and secularization by bringing painting back to a craft base.

Tuesday, April 15, 2014

Further Thoughts on Ruskin. . .

In my last blogpost I briefly addressed the issues surrounding the British Art/Social critic John Ruskin. A very old friend of mine, for whom I have a great deal of respect, was kind enough to repost that post on Facebook. A mutual friend of ours from our college days then made a lengthy comment on it, in which he felt that he needed to come to the defence of poor Ruskin. Why exactly he felt compelled to defend the old man of Brantwood escaped me entirely. Nothing I said about Ruskin was particularly controversial. I wasn’t by any means harsh on him, nor did I offer any opinions that have not been made before by people eminently more qualified than myself. Thus, I was surprised when this old acquaintance posted a defensive panegyric of Ruskin coupled with an ad homonym critique of me, calling me, and my opinion of Ruskin, “capricious.” My own capriciousness aside (and perhaps it is a fair claim), it is not entirely clear that an opinion, in and of itself, can be properly characterized by this adjective. In order to determine the capriciousness of my opinion of Ruskin, one would be required, at the very least, to have a point of comparison, which, not having talked to me about this or anything else in nearly 30 years, he decidedly did not.

However, these comments, though only superficially informed, got me thinking more closely about the problems we face when thinking about a 19th century critic like Ruskin. I wrote there that I thought that Ruskin’s ideas lacked “rigour.” And though I was not clear about what this meant, I stand by that opinion. I refer to Ruskin as lacking rigour not because he is not thorough, but rather because he depends on vague, meta-concepts about which there is no common agreement. In Ruskin’s mind, for example, great landscape painting is that which properly expresses the sublimity of God’s creation, and great art is that which reflects a certain ethical construct. One needn’t be a philosopher to understand that such concepts are overwhelmingly ambiguous. For such ideas to form part of a rigorous argument they would have to be subject to general agreement in some form. I understand, I think, what Ruskin is trying to get at some level, but the problem here is not really understanding. Ruskin was not simply trying to state his opinion, per se, he was attempting to establish a qualitative notion of art. But establishing such a theory would require agreement about the function of art as well as the subsequent criteria for quality. And agreement on such issues simply don’t prevail, let alone consensus about the nature of God or properly ‘ethical’ behaviour.

This problem is by no means exclusive to Ruskin. In fact, it is characteristic of most aesthetic philosophers. It is for this reason that qualitative theories about art largely disappeared in the 20th century. (Indecently, these points apply even more pointedly to literary theory) Meta-theories of art have been largely replaced by straight up commentary, or, at most, inter-subjective critiques of art. By inter-subjective, I mean criticizing a work of art within certain, already basically agreed upon standards. (In this sense I could, for example, critique a film by placing it squarely within a genre and then comparing it to what advocates of that genre believe are effect expressions of that particular genus of film.


I must admit that despite my somewhat ‘post-modern’ and relativistic outlook, I like Ruskin. I think my appreciation comes from the fact that I sympathize with his project of finding a qualitative theory of art. Justice Potter Stewart of the US Supreme Court once said (to paraphrase) that he couldn’t successfully define obscenity but he knew it when he saw it. I often feel the same about good art. Like a true Romantic, I want to believe that ‘great’ art is out there. It is a strange, inexplicable combination of technical skill, originality, and profound thought. The problem is that, if I am intellectually honest with myself, I am pretty sure none of these ideas can be properly defined, so like Justice Stewart, I am stuck with a platitude. And in the end, much of Ruskin’s great text Modern Painters, is just a wonderful, seductively eloquent platitude.

Wednesday, April 9, 2014

John Ruskin and the Problem of Taste. . .

I recently hit upon the idea of reading through the entire text of John Ruskin's Modern Painters. I know, it sounds crazy in the age of text messaging and audio books to actually read a five volume, 19th century text about art written in a convoluted, 18th century style. But I live on the edge, I am a daredevil. I once read an version of this book that had been edited to the bare bones of what the editor believed to be the most important excerpts - a sort of Ruskin's greatest hits. However, I decided that the time had come to take the aesthetic plunge, so to speak, and read the entire five volumes, in order to see if Ruskin's massive reputation has been well deserved.



Ruskin is often, if not usually, considered to be the most important anglo art critic of the 19th century. He is, perhaps, most renowned for his spirited defence of Turner at a time when that artist was being widely vilified. Or, perhaps, he is most famous for his rather spirited attack on the work of James Whistler and the libel case that ensured.

Ruskin suffered a number of personality drawbacks, for want of a better phrase, which has left his reputation in something of a dodgy state with many. It has often been said that he was unable to consummate his marriage with Effie Gray because his delicate sensibilities were offended at the sight of a woman in the flesh.  It seems that Ruskin's only experience with a naked woman was with marble statues, which are considerably smoother and more "ideal" than the body of a "real" woman. (Most importantly for Ruskin was, perhaps, his surprise in discovering that women, unlike marble sculptures, had body hair). Luckily for Effie, she eventually married the painter John Everett Millais, bore him eight children and seems to have had a relatively happy life. Another problem which Ruskin displayed was a typically aristocratic pompousness and overwrought sense of self-importance. Once Ruskin was convinced of the correctness of one of his philosophical postulations, he was  unable to brook disagreement.

Unfortunately for Ruskin he suffered from mental illness as he aged, (what some now believe to have been Cadasil Syndrome), and he gradually degenerated into a state of mental incapacity.

Despite his drawbacks and weaknesses, Ruskin was a profoundly interesting man. He was not only an important art critic, but he was a champion of the Arts and Crafts movement, and wrote fairly extensively about politics and society. His interesting, if somewhat naive, book Unto This Last, was an important document concerning his belief in the importance of social cooperation and the evils of industrial capitalism. Furthermore, it was a book that had a profound influence on the life of Mahatma Gandhi, who read it when he lived in South Africa and patterned much of his future political/social efforts on it.

Modern Painters was written by Ruskin in the 1840s and is considered by many to be one of the more important texts on art ever written. And though I have not gone all the way through it yet, I would say, on first blush, that it is a fairly difficult text for a 21st century reader to appreciate. It makes explicit appeals to religion which probably seem antiquated for many today and it lacks intellectual rigour. Like so many books on art, it makes huge assumption that lack argument and in the end it seems to come off, at least in part, as a very elaborate justification of a man's personal aesthetic taste. The crux of Ruskin's whole intellectual problems can be highlighted in a number of places in the first part of the first volume. I was particularly struck by the following passage made in Ruskin's preliminary discussion of the basis of art.

"Ideas of beauty, then, be it remembered, are the subjects of moral, but not intellectual, perception. By the investigation of them we shall be led to the knowledge of the ideal subjects of art."

Herein, as they say, lies the rub. One could easily argue that both of the above statements cannot be true, they are mutually exclusive.  If, as Ruskin says, ideas of beauty are really subjects of moral perception, then we would be unable to properly investigate them (or at least decide upon any 'objective' truth about them) through a process of intellectual investigation. In other words, if notions of beauty are really moral, or ethical matters, they will continually resist intellectual investigations. Put more explicitly, they will never be decided in any objective sense through rational discourse.

To put this more clearly, since no universal agreement can be found concerning ethical or normatively 'correct' behaviour, an art theory which considers art or beauty in an ethical light, will wield little to intellectual investigations. In other words, what Ruskin has done is to champion a non-rigorous, irrational field of human endeavour, to wit - morals, and then suggested that through intellectual investigations we will be able to decide upon this non-intellectual notion.

Now, some people might react to this discourse and say "Hold on here. Moral or ethical questions are not immune to intellectual investigation." And of course they are not. We might engage in a rational investigation of what someone's moral standards are. And we might, in a pinch, come to decide upon how they came about those standards. However, in the end, the correctness or incorrectness of someone's morals is not really subject of objective, intellectual discovery. Similarly, if we imagine, at some level, that a 19th century art critic like Ruskin is ultimately concerned with deciding upon the "value" or "quality" of a work of art and taste in general, then he runs into a major problem when he a priori decides that questions of beauty are really only questions of morals.

This problem goes to the very heart of much art theory and criticism. Many people talk about art in a purely exploratory manner. We can explore things like how the art affects us, what kinds of traditions the art exists in, what artists have been an influence in its production, social reception of art, etc., etc. However, obvious, and very profound problems arise when we try to make decisions about the quality of art. (Anyone who has read Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance knows this well.) Can we decide upon the quality of art beyond the relatively simple questions of skill or power of execution?? I have been investigating and thinking about this problem for over thirty years and I am no closer to a solution today than I was at the beginning.

A critic like Ruskin is convinced that he knows what constitutes "good" taste and "good" art. To justify his opinions he brings in all sorts of spiritual, religious, and moral ideas that not only seem somewhat antiquated to readers today, but are also entirely subjective matters. This is not to say that Modern Painters is a waste of paper. There is a great deal of interesting historical and semi-technical information to be found in its pages. And besides those important incentives to read Modern Painters, it must not be forgotten that Ruskin is a VERY good writer with eloquent (albeit somewhat old-fashioned) prose. If you like fine 19th century English prose, you will find few writers to rival Ruskin.

Wednesday, April 2, 2014

What, if anything, does artwork say?

In March of 1922 Lord Northbourne, a painter and etcher in his own right, sent a letter to my favourite author, E.V. Lucas in which he made the following observation: ". . . . I venture to suggest that you are on unsafe ground when you judge of an artist's temperament and personality by the characteristics of his work! It is of course an amusing and innocuous pastime, but in real life nothing has seemed stranger to me than the difference which I constantly observe between a man's work and the man himself. // I have noticed in particular that the people who paint very placid pictures are usually nervous, irritable and overstrung - perhaps they paint such pictures as antidotes? Also sometimes swashbuckling palette-knifey and brutal painters are in real life very like rabbits, or even guinea-pigs! etc., etc." Since this is the only segment of the letter which E.V. Lucas published, I can only surmise that this letter was written by Northbourne in response to Lucas' recently published, and subsequently very popular, book on Vermeer. I don't have this book readily at hand but given the remarkable placidity of Vermeer's amazing paintings I imagine that Lucas there made some strong supposition about the painter's personality.


It is easy to imagine even a rigorous historian making suppositions about the personality of the man who painted pictures like this one. Furthermore, E.V. Lucas is exceptionally placid and good-humoured in his writing and if he were going to make generalizations about someone, such assumptions would likely err on the side of serenity and quietude.

Obviously, assumptions about someone's personality are, under any circumstances, questionable. After all, most people's personalities are not easily generalized. This fact does  not, of course, prevent us from continually engaging in such generalizations. W.C. Fields was a curmudgeon, van Gogh was an emotional volcano, etc., etc. And though I don't want to deny that such generalizations are ever possible, or, indeed, useful, they are notoriously difficult to make, particularly about historical figure, people on who we largely rely upon others for our information. And of course, when we talk about someone like Vermeer, it is exceptionally difficult to make generalizations because we know so very little about him. In fact, Vermeer has been called "the Sphinx of Delft" because his life is such a mystery. Thus, talking about Vermeer's personality is an exercise in pure speculation (albeit interesting and entertaining speculation).

I am sure that all of us who produce art wonder what other might think that our work says about us as individuals. In fact most artists I have met are obsessed by the notion because, in the final analysis, it is precisely ego that drives the majority of artists. Well, I never talk about the meaning of my work and almost never talk about its content. And one of the simplest reasons for this is that such talk gets in the way of a viewer's response. I am sure that the content of someone's work does indeed say things about them as people, but exactly what is says should be left up to those who look at it.

With that in mind, here is the earliest of my paintings that I still possess, painted when I was 14 years old. (It is a watercolour and measures about 8 by 9 inches.)


And here is my latest painting, completed yesterday. (It is an oil painting on wood that measures about 24 by 18 inches.) 


I am not sure that these say anything conclusive about me as a person. But before you judge, keep in mind that they are done by the same hand that did this drawing when I was 20. 




Though there is some dispute about who said it, I leave you with the quote - "If you want to send a message, use Western Union."